Intuitive Reason that Quantifier Order Matters

Is there some understandable rationale why $\forall x\, \exists y\, P(x,y) \not \equiv \exists y\, \forall x\, P(x,y)$?

I’m looking for a sentence I can explain to students, but I am failing every time I try to come up with one.

Example

Let $P(x,y)$ mean that $x$ is greater than $y$.

  • $\forall x\, \exists y\, P(x,y)$ means that for all $x$, there is a number $y$, such that $x$ is greater than $y$.
  • $\exists y\, \forall x\, P(x,y)$ means that there is some $y$, that every number $x$ is greater than.

These don’t seem to mean different things to me. Is this perhaps an example where they do mean the same thing or am I just translating to English incorrectly?

Solutions Collecting From Web of "Intuitive Reason that Quantifier Order Matters"

Take $P(x, y)$ to mean $y$ is a parent of $x$.

Then $\forall x \exists y P(x, y)$ means everybody has a parent, while $\exists y \forall x P(x, y)$ means there is someone who is the parent of every son and daughter.

Let $P(O,C)$ mean car $C$ is owned by owner $O$.

Then $\forall C \ \exists O \ P(O,C)$ means every car has an owner.

However, $\exists O \ \forall C \ P(O,C)$ means that some owner owns all cars.

Clearly these mean different things.

Take $P(x,y)$ to be “$x$ is friends with $y$”.

One statement says ‘everyone has a friend’, the other says ‘someone is friends with everyone’.

Oops! My first answer was to the question I thought you were asking. Here is the answer to the question you actually asked: if $P(x, y)$ means $x > y$, then $\forall x \exists y P(x, y)$ is true iff there is no greatest number and $\exists y \forall x P(x, y)$ is true if there is a smallest number. Your translations into natural language are OK, but these statements are not the same: they are both true for the natural numbers, but the first is true and the second is false for the integers. So the two statements certainly don’t mean the same thing.

Order tells you the valid dependencies. For example, if we say $$\forall x \exists y P(x,y),$$

what we’re really saying is, for any $x$, we can find a $y$ dependent on that $x$ such that $P(x,y)$.

It may help to Skolemize. The formula becomes: there exists a functions $y(*)$ such that for all $x$ we have $P(x,y(x))$.

I stumbled on this page asking the same question, but I think I understand now why $\forall x\exists yP(x,y) \not\equiv \exists y\forall xP(x,y)$. It seems that the quantifiers for x and y are essentially nested in each other, such that the second quantifier is dependent on the first.

Let’s use the parent example where $P(x,y)$ is a predicate function meaning that y is the parent of x, which can also be stated that x is the child of y. Then, $\forall x\exists yP(x,y)$ can be interpreted as “For all children, there exists a parent.” Switching the order of the quantifiers gives $\exists y\forall xP(x,y)$, which can be interpreted as “For some parent, there exists all their children.” It seems that the second interpretation has the domain of children limited to the children of the parent, whereas in the first it was all children.